(Expanded from a comment on the most recent post)
The modern world is supposedly built around a scientific view of the world. If so, that would make scientists our official prophets. (Some say “priests”, but the role of the scientist is more analogous to that of the prophet than that of the priest.) One would think that, to capture the culture, having scientists on one’s side would be among the most valuable possible assets. But that’s really not the case.
Don’t get me wrong. Having scientists from one’s group is a good thing because science is worth doing: the truths it reveals are worth knowing, and the discipline it teaches is worth having. The attempt to use science in a culture war only corrupts it and produces pseudoscience. Just as a man cannot decide to learn Stoic detachment for the purpose of financial gain, scientific truth is one of those goods that can only be pursued successfully if done so for its own sake. As Bertrand Russell said about philosophy, science will answer only its own distinctive questions. However, scientists can do very little on their own to help dominate a culture. Having most scientists on one’s side is an effect of winning a culture war rather than a cause.
Consider
1) One certainly hopes that scientific discoveries do not depend on the prior beliefs of researchers. Therefore, stuffing sympathetic personnel into a field shouldn’t affect its conclusions. (If it does, it’s not real science.) A person with different loyalties might indeed investigate different questions. Religious/political demographics probably do affect research programs in the social sciences, but I doubt they are of much relevance to the real sciences. (Yes, I’m letting my prejudices show.)
2) Nor do scientists get a privileged role in interpreting their own discoveries. Nobody cared that Kepler took his model of the solar system to be itself a model of the Trinity.
Fermat, Leibniz, Maupertuis, and Euler all thought the principle of least action is a sign of God’s perfection. Eighteenth century French atheists claimed to base their worldview on Newtonian physics but took no interest in Newton’s own wacky Arian millenarianism. Descartes thought his physics had demolished 17th century materialism (his mechanical philosophy devised to emphasize how distinct are mental phenomena), just as Heisenberg thought his physics had demolished 19th century materialism (by overthrowing its epistemology), and Lemaitre thought he had destroyed the materialists’ eternal universe. Maxwell used the indistinguishability of elementary particles (atoms, for him) to advance a novel design argument.
Today, the fact that many scientists thought their discoveries were irrelevant to–or perhaps even supportive of–Christianity is regarded as a historical curiosity. The narrative imposed on the history of science since Copernicus is of the great liberation from Christian superstition. This narrative comes largely from French men of letters rather than scientists themselves; the latter having been converted to it not earlier than the late nineteenth century.
By the way, this is one reason I find seventeenth century natural philosophers so fascinating. It’s not that their beliefs about the meaning of their work were necessarily truer than the later Enlightenment and contemporary views, but that they could be so different, showing how much one’s metaphysical and historical presuppositions color how one does something so apparently nonpartisan as interpret scientific theories.
3) In any case, the philosophical interpretation of scientific theories is I think much more difficult than most people realize. Those who think it’s easy to read ontology out of physics or biology are most often reading their presuppositions into it. After nearly a century, many physicists are not shy in saying that we still don’t really understand quantum mechanics, even though it’s straightforward to use, most likely because some unacknowledged metaphysical prejudice is still being worked out of our system. As another example, that parts are ontologically prior to their wholes is an assumption which detailed scientific study of cells, atoms, etc can neither confirm nor disprove. Plato and Aristotle believed wholes to be ontologically prior, while I find the whole idea of ontological priority suspect.
4) Non-westerners encountered Western science, mores, and overwhelming technological supremacy all at once, and it was natural that they would sometimes regard them as a single package, but for Westerners it is different. Roughly our history is as follows. In the seventeenth century, Christians of various stripes carried out the scientific revolution. In the eighteenth century, atheists and deists used the success of science as an argument against Christianity. In the nineteenth century, science continued to advance, and with the Industrial Revolution, the new knowledge was now changing people’s material lives in obvious ways. Among the ranks of scientists and inventors, there was still a large diversity–Christians to atheists and everything in between. Only in the twentieth century did science clearly come to be dominated by atheists and Jews, long after some other fields had so aligned. So the West has seen science change hands and is less liable to see it as the unique genius of some faction. Being an atheist doesn’t automatically make one more “scientific” than Pascal or Maxwell.
5) Persecuting scientists doesn’t hurt one’s reputation unless one is already weak. The Left paid no price for the murder of Lavoisier or for interfering with genetics research in 20th century Russia and 21st century America. The weapon of getting to tar people as “anti-science” is not one that scientists themselves control. To be clear, I’m not recommending anyone persecute scientists, just pointing out a sad fact that one can get away with it if one’s social standing is strong. The example of Soviet science shows that one can even remain world-class in some fields (Soviet mathematics was top-rate, and of course they got most of the “firsts” in the space race) while descending into crackpottery in others.
Filed under: History of philosophy, philosophy of science | 8 Comments »