When we find a law with no lawgiver, we call it God’s law.
When we find order without an organizer, we call it creation.
When we find a justice or fittingness in the affairs of men beyond their capacity to engineer, we call it providence.
It is remarkable how naturally our mind recognizes these cases of intelligibility-beyond-intelligence and how difficult it is to devise a metaphysics in which they are at home.
It would not do to identify God as a person from whom creatures and laws are entirely separate. God’s order for the operation of beings is intrinsic to them, and His laws of righteous conduct are intrinsic to justice, but in each case they seem to transcend their subjects. At least, this is what our tendency to attribute them to God would suggest.
Nor when we speak of God’s laws, of God’s order of the world of nature and of men, do we just mean that these things appear as if imprinted by divine intelligence. It may be that these are nothing but appearances, but to say so is not to explain what we mean when we speak of them, but to deny it.
It is remarkable how unsatisfied people are with scientific explanations. They ask how something with the marks of intelligibility came to be. Give them an answer deriving it from some general principle–spontaneous symmetry breaking, detailed balance, natural selection, or whateer–and they will be disappointed. “Oh, so you’re saying it’s an accident.” In other words, if that’s the explanation, then there is no explanation. Scientists are proud of general principles that explain many phenomena, but what people are looking for is a single cause that directly imprinted this particular intelligibility.
Remarkable as well that we monotheists at least attribute all of these cases of intelligibility-without-intelligence to the same beyond-intelligence. One could say that honesty demands that I tell the truth, sobriety demands I avoid drunkenness, patriotism demands that I avoid treason, et cetera. To say that God demands all of these things is to bring them into relation with each other, that there is something inconsistent about recognizing the authority of some of these demands without recognizing the others. Similarly, the intuition of God’s created order might be one reason we so often speak of “nature” instead of “natures”, even though if we were good Aristotelians we would definitely prefer the plural.
The historical ubiquity of belief in divinity is a scandal to philosophers, perhaps especially to a believing philosopher. He does not imagine that the reasons his uneducated co-religionists could give for their beliefs would pass muster with his colleagues. And yet, he does not want to credit their faith to fortuitous error or over-hastiness. How can the common man of all ages have gotten so deep into metaphysics so easily? How could he have gotten so much right with such invalid reasoning?
There may well be an inverse relation between the logical strength of arguments for God’s existence and their attraction to the religious mind. I can’t imagine that any non-believer is troubled by an argument from morality (of the “no law without a Lawgiver” sort); arguments of this sort seem quite weak to me. But it does that the virtue of addressing God in a way that believers actually conceive and relate to Him, and so no less figures than Newman and Lewis understood its power.
I think the common intuitions are valid, although by themselves they hardly constitute proof, are hardly even clear enough to know what they might be proof of. I doubt we ever cease to rely on them, at least as a check on our reasoning.
Filed under: Uncategorized | 3 Comments »